Supposing the other letters have not been about love, this
one makes its proclamation to the contrary. In a final essay, a student of mine
(CC) wrote about the perspective of the object in relation to Margery William’s
story, The Velveteen Rabbit or How Toys
Become Real. It’s easy to see from the very beginning, how inanimateness or
deadness is taken as preceding existence or presence in the world, and that
also places emphasis on the use of the term “object” in relation to people;
what seems to be a metaphor-concept for people is perhaps more than that
already. As CC describes, the rabbit emerges as an object through processes of “real”
abstraction, which demonstrate the ways in which its being acted upon is a
means of its becoming worn, its “fraying,” a term Derrida takes up from Freud
in “Freud and the Scene of Writing” (thanks CM for this reference). The
difficulty of grasping this process (not just a matter of understanding but of touching/taking
hold of/feeling) has a correlate, as CC notes, in Winnicott’s discussion of
object relating vs. object use: “Within the context of Winnicott’s
understanding of object use there seems to be an implication that object usage
is equitable to the love of an object; that the child must destroy the object
so that it can love the object, or that in loving the object the child destroys
the object. One cannot love an object that they cannot accept is an ‘entity in
its own right’ and not simply a ‘bundle of projections,’ for the love of the
self-made projected object is simply the love of oneself (Winnicott 118-120).”
It’s Williams’s story that adds the terms of love explicitly, and CC’s paper
identifies and lingers over these terms.
In thinking about this, I’m interested in how this process of
destructiveness “places the object outside,” which is the moment responsible
for the object becoming an “entity in its own right,” about which there is an
implicit priority. In other scenes, such a placing “outside” is a gesture that
is protective or defensive on one side and hallucinatory on the other, part of
the distorted perspective of mental abstraction, which registers in complicity’s
desire to see oneself there simply so that an “outside” can be experienced or
felt as non-illusory. I’m interested in how this constitutive relation detailed
in the Winnicottian scene relates to the otherwise protective /defensive gesture.
Perhaps, as Balint describes, this indifferentiation accounts for the primacy
of primary love, which disregards the object totally. But this prevalence
raises a question about the implicit value placed on the “entity in its own
right.” If this common work of putting something “outside” brings complicity
and love into relation, it’s interesting that love becomes significant because
it carries the possibility of feeling that complicity otherwise denies. Love
(perhaps here it’s useful to re-invoke preference as Vor-liebe (although below Derrida will cite Freud as using “Bevorzugung)) is able to shore up the
inadequacy of complicity not because it is reparative but because it reveals
itself (from the perspective of the object) as destructive. This is a possible
explanation of how the protective or defensive aspect of complicity also wants
to hide from or de-link its destructiveness so that one can continue to love
oneself (through others). Maybe that’s much the course of things but I feel
radically uninclined in this way.
How to love that which is real about the object, when what
is real is the process only of fraying? Derrida writes,
“An equality in resistances to the fraying or an equivalence in the forces fraying would eliminate any preference in choice of itinerary. Memory would be paralysed. It is the difference between frayings which is the real origin of memory and thus of the psyche. Only that difference frees a “preference of path” (Wegbevorzugung): ‘Memory is represented’ (dargestellt) by the differences in the frayings between y-neurones.’ We must then not say that fraying without difference is insufficient for memory; it must be stipulated that there is no pure fraying without difference.”
Memory’s being the “very essence” of the psyche accounts for
this imperative. This stipulation turns away, as does Williams’s story, from
the Lacanian real as hole or lack. If there is only fraying with difference, we
might also say that there is only loving as becoming real, but then how is it
that we must also account for so much brokenness, deception, misdirection,
errant and irreversible fraying in these processes, when “fraying with
difference” seems to displace the insufficiency of conceptualizing “fraying without
difference”? Thinking about what is being frayed in this differentiating moment
draws me back to CC’s earlier questions about the found/created distinction.
Perhaps this is a site of violence (in contrast to destructiveness) where there
is played out the demand of this question repeatedly. What if you were to see the
processes repeated, the movement of this repetition, even against the seductive
appearance of it being for the first time? Is this “entity in its own right”
something encountered along the Wegbevorzugung
or not, I wonder? And what is the difference between the “preference of path” (Wegbevorzugung) and “fraying” (Bahnung), the “breaking of a path (Bahn)”?
No comments:
Post a Comment