Paolo Virno`s ``Virtuosity and Revolution`` pursues some of the lines I have been trying to draw between Arendt`s take on the ``subjective illusion,``
the contradiction between freedom and necessity, and the Marxist
concern with the contradiction within the subjective modes of
reproduction and productive to capitalism. Resolving such a
contradiction on the side of a productive subject who is resistant,
autonomous Marxist theorists such Cesare Casarino, Hardt and Negri, and
Virno, posit the notion of the ``common`` as a way of thinking about
positive models of subjective resistance. Casarino writes, ``To claim
back and seize the common as production entails a drastic reorientation
of subjectivity.... It entails the production of a form of subjectivity constituted by a counterdesire. Such a counterdesire is the desire to be in common--as
opposed to the desire to be for the common-as-negated-by-capital, the
desire to be captive of one`s own negation--in short, as opposed to the desire not to be``
(17). Such theories, which prescribe a mode of subjectivity,
implicitly--or explicitly, as Casarino--corralling reason and desire,
are predicated upon an opposition to the Arendtian model of
subjectivity, or rather, the liberal subject that is assumed to be the
model or the outcome of Arendt`s ideas about work, labor, and political
activity.
Virno`s essay makes clear how central the
opposition to Arendt is to work on the common, since, as he claims,
```To each his own` seems to be the message of Arendt`s The Human Condition,
and every man for himself...the other two fundamental spheres, work and
intellect, remain unchanged in their quantitative structures`` (206). Virno uses Arendt as an (or the) example of unfettered individualism, figured first as a feature of the intellect and then as a figure of work.
Virno`s claim that this is what Arendt is doing is built upon the idea
that she ``rejects out of hand the very idea of a public intellect``
(193). Conflating the ``life of the mind`` with the private sphere,
Virno wrongly concludes that the intellect--which includes thought,
willing, and judging, according to The Life of the Mind--does not entail a ``care for common concerns`` (Virno 193). As both The Life of the Mind and her Lectures on Kant`s Political Philosophy
demonstrate, however, the care for common concerns turns out to be the
central thesis of our intellectual life. What is perhaps more immediate
to my concerns here is not this interpretive argument, but rather the
noticeable absence of the term ``labor`` from Virno`s analysis of
Arendt.
The absence of labor is all the more notable in
light of Sylvia Federici`s critique of autonomous Marxists` work on the
subject of immaterial labor, ``Precarious Labor: A Feminist Viewpoint.``
More particularly, the points that Federici claims to be missing from
this work--namely that ``capitalist development is always at the same
time a process of underdevelopment,`` and that unpaid reproductive labor
continues to remain unrecognized, despite feminist analysis of the
sexual division of labor--can be seen to be functions of the same type
of disregard that is paid Arendt. For in Arendt`s case, labor involves
exactly the realm of unwaged labor and the uneven development of freedom
to which Federici refers. In her discussion of the private and public
realm in The Human Condition, Arendt writes: ``What all Greek philosophers, no matter how opposed to polis
life, took for granted is that freedom is exclusively located in the
political realm, that necessity is primarily a prepolitical phenomenon,
characteristic of the private household organization, and that force and
violence are justified in this sphere because they are the only means
to master necessity--for instance, by ruling over slaves--and to become
free`` (31). Later in this same section, she describes how the private
realm, far from being a realm that individuals could choose (over, say,
the common or the public realm) is the realm of labor: ``Hidden away
were the laborers who `with their bodies minister to the [bodily] needs
of life` and the women who with their bodies guarantee the physical
survival of the species. Women and slaves belonged to the same category
and were hidden away not only because they were somebody else`s property
but because their life was `laborious,` devoted to bodily functions``
(72). These lines from Arendt describe how the freedom of the worker is
dependent upon a realm of necessity--whether his own or the necessary
labor of another--from which he cannot become free. It is her concern
with the effects of feeling that one is free--the justification of
``force and violence``--that inform her insistence of making visible the
distinction between labor and work.
While the
distinctions between private and public or between labor and work
themselves may be belabored, Arendt`s distinctions in general--such as
between ``necessity and freedom,`` ``futility and permanence,`` ``shame
and honor`` (73)--they do not serve prescriptive purposes, as I
indicated above in the case of the Marxist subject, but rather they work
to retain other distinctions that runs across and within both
categories (see, for example, unquiet/quiet distinction, HC 15). Arendt`s concern is not only that as work ``assumes the character of labor,`` the value of work (its permanence, the durable world it creates) is denigrated, but that no longer being able to see necessity,
the private realm, has its own consequences. In this regard, it remains
for Arendt crucial that man knows ``he is subject to necessity,`` since
in contrast to ``life in slavery,`` ``this condition [of being subject
to need and necessity] is no longer fully manifest and its lack of
appearance has made it much more difficult to notice and remember``
(121). But why is it that Arendt finds it so important to maintain the
perceptibility of the private realm, which is indeed that realm which is
about ``privation,`` about the ``life processes`` which are
``futile``because they appear and disappear? Is it the easing of this
``repugnance to futility`` (121) that she seeks, or, in fact, its
opposite? It is the figure of ``socialized mankind,`` the indistinction
between society and the life-processes themselves, that presents a
threat large enough to defend against with the insistence on maintaining
the perceptibility of the private realm.
In Arendt`s
conceptualization, the private realm is like ``the other, dark and
hidden side of the public realm`` (64), and thus perception of it, or
the ability to perceive it does not have the same qualities as
perception in public life, which is built around being among others. The
perception of the private entails the capacity to see what is ``no
longer human`` about human existence, to see that ``man exist[s] in this
sphere not as a truly human being but only as a specimen of the animal
species man-kind`` (46). And while it is true that Arendt does not
elevate the capacity to perceive this to the realm of action, its clear
function is to preserve the ambivalence within ``futility``--its not
only that futility is to be guarded against, as indicated by the danger
of the phenomenon of ``loneliness`` (59, which in The Origins of Totalitarianism has consequences for
terror), or by the threatened reality of a world that appears
impermanent--but the idea that the feeling of ``futility`` is one that
provides individuals with the ``strongest impulse`` toward liberation
(and thus also toward mastery, violence, and force). The ambivalent
treatment of futility in the private realm has to do with the fact that
registering it is like registering the desire not to be. That
this still follows a model in which the darker ground is given meaning
by ``rising into sight,`` does not minimize the potential for thinking
about the impacts of losing what Arendt calls the ``non-privative traits
of privacy``: ``a life spent entirely in public, in the presence of
others, becomes, as we would say, shallow. While it retains its
visibility, it loses that quality of rising into sight from some darker
ground which must remain hidden if it is not to lose its depth in a very
real, non-subjective sense`` (71).
Wednesday, September 5, 2012
Wednesday, August 15, 2012
the necessity of irresistibility
In The Micro-Politics of Capital, Jason Read describes the contradiction that is raised for the subject between “the total subjection of sociality and subjectivity to capital and the concomitant development of a subjective and social power irreducible to abstract labor” (119). Read points to a contradiction that gels into the problem of “thinking resistance” (11). I approach the problem of the production of subjectivity, in Read’s terms, of the “more than one” (Balibar’s transinidividual) from a different perspective, which is rooted in Arendt’s critical insight about how the “more than” of preference is not opposed to necessity, but rather, in its capacity to will or choose against the given, remains able to provoke necessity, to see the violence behind necessity. Preference, the “styles, desires, communities, and ways of communicating” (147), to use Read’s phrasing, that become productive in “real subsumption” do not represent a depature from the “necessities of “bare life’” (147), nor do they represent the shift or temporal progression from one mode of production to another; rather, these “preferences” are there from the beginning, first registered as qualities destroyed in “primitive accumulation,” by the “violence necessary to destroy precapitalist social relations” (14). The destruction of preferences is actually, however, the creation of “needs and wants,” the transformation of the oppressive violence of the master into the violence which is there is the force of necessity. Arendt’s interest in preference is linked to her abiding concern with “the beginning,” and with the potential for freedom that is created in this moment of expropriation, the unearthing of what appears as natural or necessary as man-made and political. Arendt describes this as Marx’s most explosive contribution, but following Hegelian turn, in which the recovery of the “ability to act,” which now places laborers under their “daily needs and wants” (53) makes action “irresistible,” not any longer from a feeling of “being violated,” but “by virtue of the very necessity under which emancipation had put the working class” (53).
Arendt’s critique of Marx in On Revolution and The Human Condition and her copious discussions of the thinking individual make her unpopular among theorists of the revolutionary subject. In fact, Arendt is often with the assumption of the liberal subject, but it is more accurate to say that Arendt hits upon the contradictions between the liberal subject and the revolutionary, proposing that the problem of this subject is not, as it has long been assumed, getting rid of the “responsible and isolated subject.” For Arendt, the illusion of the individual subject is necessary (or inevitable) and attempts to do away with it—to reveal how the singular “I” is a collective “We”—end up circling around the problems of agency invoked by this formulation. For Arendt, this illusion is a false problem (Scheinproblem), one whose calls for demystification end up contributing to a mystification that is far worthier of being demystified: the confusion of being at once spectators and actors and the tendency to mistake spectating for acting. It is this illusion, according to Arendt, that allows liberal and revolutionary subjects alike to develop a political morality grounded in the certainty of the self. Whereas this illusion can be disentangled from what appears as historical or economic necessity, the persistence of that other subjective illusion—of the “I”’s feeling that she is a singular one with wants and needs—reveals how “necessary” this articulation is to the concept of freedom.
Preference does not involve becoming free from this necessity, but continually unearths the violent, non-natural premises of necessity, developing the capacity to intervene in this necessity by foregrounding the role of the spectator—our role as spectators—even when it is more compelling to understand ourselves as actors. Arendt’s ideas about preference end up illuminating her discussion of how terror results when necessity replaces freedom, and these insights are significant—not only because of the implicit warning, but because the discussion makes an argument for a opposition of art and politics, based on the what has been seen to happen choices become mistaken as criterion for the endpoint of revolution. The opposition of art and politics is not, as first it may seem, an argument for an apolitical aesthetics. Quite the opposite: the aesthetic is unearthed as a political moment; this unearthing is what I will refer to as aesthetic activity, for it is—quite akin to discussion of the subject—about “recover[ing] its ability to act.” But in being read as political, this artistic “choice” does not, of course, become necessarily political or become a “criterion” for political activity.
picture: Marsha Cottrell,
Monday, July 9, 2012
recovering poems
Austerity remarks to closure
minus breathing room
take your beautiful words and fuck this
pretend you did not see shadows
in the street at half past
mid hour, to be precise
pretend, tell yourself, these conditions
elide, elusive. [i have a small child
now, interrupting]. Didn`t you want
help, to help someone?
minus breathing room
take your beautiful words and fuck this
pretend you did not see shadows
in the street at half past
mid hour, to be precise
pretend, tell yourself, these conditions
elide, elusive. [i have a small child
now, interrupting]. Didn`t you want
help, to help someone?
Friday, May 11, 2012
proposal-ing
The revised Estranging Lyric proposes to examine the emergence of civilian guilt as one of the
dominant modes in which the moral regime of financial capitalism comes to be
developed out of the framework of postwar Europe. I argue that poetry creates a
space in which the discourse of political morality becomes discernible, first,
because the subject of poetry figures centrally in how the postwar dialectic of
culture and barbarism reaches its so-called last stage, and second, because the
processes of identification that become perceptible in this “crisis of lyric
agency” map onto the crises of political activity experienced after the second
world war. In short, the lyric “I” becomes a cipher for reading the newly construed
“bystander,” who arose as the model of the world citizen after the 1948
Universal Declaration of Human Rights.
Part of the work of
the book is to develop the terms for talking about this postwar period, in which,
I argue, the terms of “culture” and the “economy” are developed together. In
this book, I propose a strong reading of the “postwar,” problematizing
characterizations of the period as the aftermath of trauma. Instead, I focus on
how economic restructuring gets taken up through figures of guilt and
responsibility. The unique focus of my project lies in approaching the
discursive aspect of guilt and considers how this period yields the
simultaneous constitution and crisis of the liberal bourgeois subject as the
subject of lyric poetry. The situation
of this discussion around the figure of war isolates the problem of violence
and representation by establishing barbarism as the term through which the
continuity of European fascism and imperialism can be thought. In contrast to
books that explore postwar culture as a problem or crisis of representation,
this book addresses the continuity of aggression in the postwar through the
construction of morality.
There are many historical pinpoints that elicit periods and
readings of the “postwar” period, and there are multiple aspects of the
restructuring processes, including the global economic policies put forth in Bretton
Woods in 1944 implemented later in 1958, the Marshall Plan, the creation of the
IMF and World Bank, the restructuring of defeated countries and the
organization of Cold War states, decolonization, and wars of national
liberation. Now, it is possible to see this all as the unfolding of capitalism,
of neo-liberal economic policies, and to see it not as something inevitable, but
as something with pronounced turning points throughout. Accompanying these
discontinuous developments of today’s late capitalist world, are the moral and
ethical positions that not only keep pace with development, but present us with
the very capacity to make sense of historical periods. This is crucial: it is
crucial that the construction of morality and the distribution of ethical
behavior are not just the ideological underpinning of these economic and
structural forms of violence, but that they are the very means by which we can claim to be able to see
something like the system from the position of the system, to see the very
materiality and immateriality of labor. The arc that forms connecting one plotted
point to the next coincides with a necessity that appears narrative.
The question I approach is thus an inversion of one that is
often posed elsewhere, such as Christopher Nealon’s notion in his article “Value| Theory | Crisis” (PMLA 127.1 (Jan 2012)101-106) that it is “not the pursuit of a transcendental vantage point or
the critique of that pursuit but the relentless surveying of possible grounds
for solidarity among those for whom the regime of capital spells only suffering”
(106, cites after During 115). The turn to poetry made recently and explicitly
by Nealon and by Joshua Clover (whose essay of the same title also appears in this
issue of PMLA, pages 107-114), as a response to the narrative (and I would say
performative) supremacy of the linguistic turn (and post-structuralism),
involves thinking about the suitability of poetry as a form to deal with the
contradictions of “value theory” (Clover 110).
Acknowledging, as Nealon does
above, that the pursuit of the subject and its critique are one and the same,
his positing of a third, of the “solidarity [of] … suffering,” raises similar
contradictions about how to think of the position of subjectivity. If Nealon
exhibits “the optimism of the will,” Clover, in his own phrase, inhabits “the
delusion of the intellect” (Clover 113), something that, if I am to read him
correctly, is only a good thing. Postwar poetry too has a lot to say about the
tension that holds between the collective “we” and the individually deluded “I,”
and more explicitly about the claims that are made to either of these
positions. It is for good reason that Adorno maintains the tension and
distinction between individual and collective identifications--not, of course,
to place one above the other, but because
of this very tension, which is at the heart of the production of morality.
The value of addressing the terms of identification in
poetry is that it opens up questions about how we can theorize the crisis of
agency and also possibilities of subjectivity. These are important because they
concern “the subjective life-world of labor” (Clover 111). If it is true that
poetry is better equipped to deal with the “axial transmutation” of price into
value, as Clover claims, or with “passing off time as space,” it is not because
it has resolved and put behind the debates and discussion surrounding poetry in
Europe in the 40s and 50s, and in the U.S. in the 60s and 70s, which track the
emergence of the problem of the subject. By “problem,” I mean, perhaps, what
Jason Read has identified in The Micro-politics of Capital: Marx and the prehistory of the Present as the “philosophical”
nature of the mode of production, which Read emphasizes is not “just another name
for economy or society,” but relates to the production of consciousness and
subjectivity (6). My study of poetry develops this aspect of Marxist and poetic
thought, proposing that the lyric “I” is a cipher for this problem of
subjective agency.
The experience of feeling “haunted,” which Clover describes in
“Autumn of the System: Poetry and Financial Capital” (Journal of Narrative Theory
41.1 (Spring 2011) 34-52) as akin to Jameson’s account of the “waning of
affect,” is the experiential grasp of this subtraction: “the feeling of M-M’; haunted by the C to
come” (Clover 46). The experience of this haunting has a correlate in postwar
writing on the problem of civilian guilt. Different, and yet not unrelated to
mourning, or the working through of the atrocity of the Holocaust, civilian
guilt involves thinking about the limits of language, that is, precisely those
points at which things become unsayable. Normally read through trauma theory,
the unsayable also pertains to the intractability of the moral and economic and
to be more precise to the figure of indeterminacy and delusion that is well-taken
by the “I” in postwar lyric. My thesis is that the crisis of agency in the
lyric speaker of postwar poetry corresponds to the experience of civilian
guilt. Civilian guilt, in the figure of the bystander, in turn, becomes the
founding narrative of postwar reconstruction; it describes how subjects experience
the postwar but it also involves the subject’s capacity to maintain the
delusion of a moral regime that accompanies capital’s global expansion.
Postwar poetry makes the argument that wartime aggression continues
into daily life, that it becomes everyday. But this argument is supplanted by
another, more critical discourse, which notes a similar phenomenon. This critical
postwar poetry regards the continuation of aggression into society as the
extension of European imperialism and thus as the continued project of European
self-making. These “I”s are thus critical of both reconstruction and the denunciation
of aggression because they are two sides of the same construction of morality.
The project is thus to think about the genealogy of the bystander, the guilty
civilian, who becomes the figure of morality that accompanies the regime of
postwar globalized capital. There are reasons to locate this figure in the
context of Germany. The bystander, I propose, is not immediately the liberal
subject, but the barbarity of bystanding becomes internalized or introjected;
it provides us with a model for thinking about the problems of the liberal
subject that is no merely not-not-a-collective, and by taking the conflict
between ethical and transcendental subject head on.
Labels:
bystander,
dissertation,
guilt,
human rights,
poetry,
postwar
Friday, May 4, 2012
graucats
in night
all cats are gray
all dreaming generalizations
are equally guilty
in dark in time
all cats are becoming
gray
zones of dark times, eventuating
and we are all equally guilty
in night
in dark times
by night all cats look gray
(to me?) I to you to he/she/it
to we you all they
they are gray, indiscriminate
plucked from the sea of shade
for posterity.
is this what the big party is all about?
returning them in their little parts
(P.A.R.T.S.) to the sea
to shades
of gray cats
[the red square, the concrete plaza
(the grass will not do
) the closet will not do
felt. wares.
the little red felt square
wears the gray
cat
by night.
reference: Lyndsey Stonebridge, The Writing of Anxiety, gray cat/Marx, most recently.
all cats are gray
all dreaming generalizations
are equally guilty
in dark in time
all cats are becoming
gray
zones of dark times, eventuating
and we are all equally guilty
in night
in dark times
by night all cats look gray
(to me?) I to you to he/she/it
to we you all they
they are gray, indiscriminate
plucked from the sea of shade
for posterity.
is this what the big party is all about?
returning them in their little parts
(P.A.R.T.S.) to the sea
to shades
of gray cats
[the red square, the concrete plaza
(the grass will not do
) the closet will not do
felt. wares.
the little red felt square
wears the gray
cat
by night.
reference: Lyndsey Stonebridge, The Writing of Anxiety, gray cat/Marx, most recently.
Monday, April 30, 2012
being born later
In his recent book, The Bonds of Debt, Richard Dienst devotes a couple of paragraphs to Bertolt Brecht`s poem, ``An die Nachgeborenen.`` It is actually Benjamin who Dienst is discussing, and in particular a phrase of Benjamin`s that is often difficult to locate, and may in fact only be represented here in fragments: ``for the sake of the hopeless, we are given hope.`` Dienst describes Benjamin`s awareness of the schizophrenic organization of the Jetztzeit, that ``complex interval between wishful expectation and dread, teaching us to practice different modalities of anticipation and suspension, long patience and outright refusal (166),`` connecting Benjamin`s notes on Brecht`s poem to these ``conflicted moods`` (166, Dienst`s words). Benjamin`s notes read:
[line scratched out:] Example of genuine historical representation: `An die Nachgeborenen.` We claim from those born later not thanks for our victories but rather remembrance for our defeats. [not scratched out:] That is consolation: the only kind that can be given to those who have no more hope for consolation. (Dienst 166)The footnote attributes this passage to Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schriften Band I/iii (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag), p. 1,240), and although it is not the passage that I mention above, the common theme of consolation, from which Dienst distills an idea about remembering defeat, and in fact, establishing continuity on the basis of notions of defeat or failure. These grounds of ``infinite indebtedness,`` which for Dienst also refer to the phenomenological aspects of the given, aspects that qualify it not as inert or fixed, but as fluid, ``to be drawn out in our encounter with it,`` form the basis of the types of political subjectivity that Dienst imagines possible.
Dienst`s point of departure suggests that thinking in dark times has to do with negotiating this point of historical continuity and transition. In the last lines of the poem, Brecht writes,
The lines anticipate the perspective of historical judgment, proposing that the consolation is not only a form of historical forgiveness, but that such a position of spectatorship is central to the formulation of subjects who take up the project that Brecht (or Dienst or Benjamin) describes. Brecht`s seemingly straightforward caveat is also contorted by his effort throughout the poem to articulate the limits of speaking in dark times. And although his poems tend to be organized around the themes of state oppression and class conflict, they articulate less visible arguments about political agency. In actuality, they articulate the struggles of the bourgeois subject, struggles that become presented and seemingly resolved in terms of morality, and predominantly, in terms of complicity. If complicity is the only way that the bourgeois subject experiences political agency, the problem (and its solution) is not that to deal with the problem of debt we must refuse the morality of guilt and personal responsibility that accompanies it, or that, as Nietzsche found, guilt produces bad morality, but that the refusal of guilt as a form of moral or ethical activity or the construction of an alternative (take for example, Timothy Bewes` promotion of ``shame`` in his book, The Event of Postcolonial Shame) is an expression of its very centrality in conceptualizing political agency. Brecht is the great thinker of this bourgeois guilt, the thing that keeps the bourgeoisie from being able to identify as proletarians, and this is also why the problem of morality is one of identification. In other words, the circularity of refusal and recuperation works much like the aesthetic identification that is the object of Brecht`s critique. Projects that articulate the possibility of ``refusing guilt,`` or ``refusing debt,`` are thus not that far from Brecht`s project refusing aesthetic identification, and there can be something to take from his determinations of complicity.Think—When you speak of our weaknesses,
Also of the dark timeThat brought them forth.
picture: Selected Poems by Bertolt Brecht, cover by Roy Kuhlman (Grove Press, 1959).
Labels:
brecht,
complicity,
dark times,
debt,
ideology
Saturday, April 14, 2012
R/hode I/sland, P/rovidence
This series of photographs is meant, in ways, to be a response to this running water is death, a film presented by Rei Terada at the ACLA plenary session (March 31, 2012), Thinking Disaster, and to the ACLA panels and Providence encountered there, and perhaps in particular to the continuing and profound conversations with Michelle Cho (missing Travis Tanner and Annette Rubado, of course). In ways, it was as if everything in the past ten years had wound up to this point, and the images that follow are all taken relatively blindly, from the car as I was driving away through Rhode Island. It was the driving away that was inevitable. |
Call it a happy accident; the question is why frame action in this way? Even above, you can see how it tends to the edges, already suggesting that there is something to see like the womb in abyss... |
Sometimes, it is the foregrounding of coincidence that makes perceptible the continual registration of ``phenomenal death,`` of death already. |
He had, after all, stated that the Arendtian liberal model needed to be ``heavily worked on.`` |
Then, there was another discussion about ``underdevelopment.`` |
Which I understood as a form of disaster, something like the logical, but irrational, underside of development. |
As where we are when we are between the necessary and the intolerable. |
At least from there we can think about figures of resistance without feeling we are obliged to do away with the beauty of decrepit buildings. |
In this room, we arrived at three terms for signifying a form of community ``after the subject``: ad hoc, emergent, and spontaneous. |
For example, if you would believe it, I took this picture because I kept wanting to capture the ---. |
In other words, value is no longer aligned with aesthetics, but with production. |
But all things point towards retrospection, as what is inevitable. For Joshua Clover, this has something to do with line break, ``the dominant formal fact of poetics.`` |
I am less inclined. |
Labels:
activity,
aesthetics,
arendt,
art,
photographs,
spectator,
unraveling
Monday, February 27, 2012
the ou mallon
Georgio Agamben`s discussion of the Skeptic term ou mallon (``no more than``) provides ground for theorizing the Arendtian notion of preferring-as-discrimination, which she introduces in her discussion of taste as a political activity in ``The Crisis in Culture.`` Agamben describes how the ou mallon functions in the Skeptic tradition as the radical ``suspension`` of possibility: ``no more this than that.`` The upshot of this is for potentiality, which is ultimately what Agamben wants (the essay which includes this term, ``Bartleby, or on Contingency,`` is published in his book Potentialities. But potentiality is not as much about the future as about the past--about saving ``what was not.`` Agamben thus finds fault with Nietzsche`s captivation with the liberatory aspect of being able to will backwards. Agamben writes, ``This is why Zarathustra is the one who teaches the will to `will backwards` (zurueckwollen) and to transform every `thus it was` into a `thus I willed it`: `this alone is liberation.` Solely concerned with repressing the spirit of revenge, Nietzsche completely forgets the laments of what was not or could have been otherwise`` (``Bartleby`` 267). Agamben, who mentions Deleuze`s essay on Bartleby (``Bartleby, or the Formula``) in his own essay, does not draw out the connection between ``willing backwards`` and Deleuze`s idea of the automatic passage of the two phases of Bartleby`s refusal into one another, but together, these form the logic of preferring-as-willing. In models of this logic, preferring is seen to be a form of willing. Although she does not fully articulate this in her effort to distinguish between preferring and willing, Arendt`s concern about how freedom is surrendered to necessity even in willing guides her conceptualization of a liberatory moment that does not make this exchange. Arendt`s criticism of Marx for eventually surrendering freedom to necessity, which arises from her belief that freedom needs to be preserved as a social right, anticipates the problematic treatment of the transitional and transitory phenomenon of social change in the work of Deleuze, Zizek, and others who raise Bartleby to the position of a figure of revolution.
In my effort to articulate how the Arendtian preferring-as-discrimination functions as distinct from the above logic of preference, I take recourse through the figure/ground problem, which foregrounds (so to speak) the problem of discerning to whom boundary lines pertain, and thus of making judgments about what constitutes object and what context, what activity and what passivity, what artistic and what aesthetic, and so on... Agamben`s discussion of the ou mallon helps to make the case for Arendt`s version because he is also interested in substantializing the loss, not as an object, but as a continuation of the problem of what constitutes the overlap between artistic and aesthetic activity. In the series of essays published in The Man Without Content, Agamben takes up the issue of the split between genius (and artistic production) and taste (and aesthetic judgment) which Arendt also discusses in her lectures on Kant`s political philosophy. Preferring-as-discrimination thus denotes a realm of aesthetic activity, in which individuals are called upon to be both spectators and actors. As Arendt found, this complex and oftentimes confusing state marks human experience in the world. Her elevation of judging as the highest form of political activity derives from her idea about individuals as ``world spectators,`` including the notions of sociality and communicability that follow from being public beings. Arendtian necessity comes in, however, in the idea of the ``dark times,`` and her imposition of this term to describe periods of ``foreordained doom`` curtails the freedom that should be attainable in this sphere. The ``dark times,`` it begins to seem, are not a period, but something like the obverse of that revolutionary and free spontaneous beginning, the darkness into which figures recede and withdraw.
Arendt does not go so far as to develop these ideas about aesthetic activity, and her discussion of the political aspect of aesthetics does not involve the conflict with the artistic in the sense that Agamben wants and that, thirty-six years after her death, is more clearly invoked in the spectator society of the late twentieth- and early twenty-first centuries.
pictures: winter, Minnesota (2010); Nasreen Mohamedi, Untitled (drawing)
Labels:
activity,
arendt,
aristotle,
blind contour,
passivity,
preference,
Trockel
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)